Heidegger, Martin

Heidegger, Martin
born Sept. 26, 1889, Messkirch, Schwarzwald, Ger.
died May 26, 1976, Messkirch, W.Ger.

German philosopher.

He taught at the universities of Marburg (1923–27) and Freiburg (1927–44). In 1927 he published his magnum opus, Being and Time. It strongly influenced Jean-Paul Sartre and other existentialists, and, despite Heidegger's protestations, he was classed as the leading atheistic existentialist. His declared purpose in the work was to raise anew the question of the meaning of being. His preliminary analysis of human existence (Dasein, or "being-there") employed the method of phenomenology. In the early 1930s his thought underwent a Kehre ("turning around"), which some have seen as an abandonment of the problem of Being and Time. Heidegger joined the Nazi Party in 1933 and supported Hitler's policies as rector of Freiburg (1933–34) and less actively through the end of the war. His complicity with the Nazis, which he never publicly disavowed, has prompted debates about whether his philosophy is inherently "totalitarian." Heidegger's work strongly influenced hermeneutics and poststructuralism.

Martin Heidegger.

Camera Press

* * *

▪ German philosopher
Introduction
born September 26, 1889, Messkirch, Schwarzwald, Germany
died May 26, 1976, Messkirch, West Germany
 German philosopher, counted among the main exponents of Existentialism. His groundbreaking work in ontology and metaphysics determined the course of 20th-century philosophy on the European continent and exerted an enormous influence in virtually every other humanistic discipline, including literary criticism, hermeneutics, psychology, and theology.

Background and youth
      The son of a Roman Catholic sexton, Heidegger showed an early interest in religion. Intending to become a priest, he began theological studies at the University of Freiburg (Freiburg, Albert Ludwig University of) in 1909 but switched to philosophy and mathematics in 1911. His interest in philosophy dated from at least 1907, however, when he undertook an intensive study of Von der mannigfachen Bedeutung des Seienden nach Aristoteles (1862; “On the Manifold Meaning of Being According to Aristotle”) by the 19th-century German philosopher Franz Brentano (Brentano, Franz).

      Brentano's work in ontology helped to inspire Heidegger's lifelong conviction that there is a single, basic sense of the verb “to be” that lies behind all its varied usages. From Brentano Heidegger also developed his enthusiasm for the ancient Greeks—especially the pre-Socratics. In addition to these philosophers, Heidegger's work is obviously influenced by Plato, Aristotle, the Gnostic (Gnosticism) philosophers of the 2nd century AD, and several 19th- and early 20th-century thinkers, including the early figures of existentialism, Søren Kierkegaard (Kierkegaard, Søren) and Friedrich Nietzsche (Nietzsche, Friedrich); Wilhelm Dilthey (Dilthey, Wilhelm), who was noted for directing the attention of philosophers to the human and historical sciences; and Edmund Husserl (Husserl, Edmund), the founder of the phenomenological (Phenomenology) movement in philosophy.

      While still in his 20s, Heidegger studied at Freiburg with Heinrich Rickert (Rickert, Heinrich), the leading figure of the axiological school of neo- Kantianism, and with Husserl, who was then already famous. Husserl's phenomenology, and especially his struggle against the intrusion of psychologism into traditionally philosophical studies of man, determined the background of the young Heidegger's doctoral dissertation, Die Lehre vom Urteil im Psychologismus: Ein kritisch-positiver Beitrag zur Logik (“The Doctrine of Judgment in Psychologism: A Critical-Positive Contribution to Logic”; 1914). Consequently, what Heidegger later said and wrote about anxiety, thinking, forgetfulness, curiosity, distress, care, and awe was not meant as psychology; and what he said about man, publicness, and other-directedness was not intended to be sociology, anthropology, or political science. His utterances were meant to disclose ways of Being.

Philosophy
      Heidegger began teaching at the University of Freiburg during the winter semester of 1915 and wrote his habilitation thesis on the 13th-century English Franciscan philosopher Duns Scotus (Duns Scotus, John). As a colleague of Husserl, Heidegger was expected to carry the phenomenological movement forward in the spirit of his former master. As a religiously inclined young man, however, he went his own way instead. While serving as a professor ordinarius at Marburg University (1923–28), he astonished the German philosophical world with Being and Time (1927). Although almost unreadable, it was immediately felt to be of prime importance, whatever its relation to Husserl might be. In spite of—and perhaps partly because of—its intriguingly difficult style, Being and Time was acclaimed as a masterpiece not only in German-speaking countries but also in Latin ones, where phenomenology was well established. It strongly influenced Jean-Paul Sartre (Sartre, Jean-Paul) and other existentialists in France, and on the basis of this work Heidegger came to be regarded as the leading atheistic existentialist, though he always rejected that label. The reception of Being and Time in the English-speaking world was chilly, however, and its influence there was negligible for several decades.

      Heidegger's declared purpose in Being and Time is to show what it means for a person to be—or, more accurately, how it is for a person to be. This task leads to a more fundamental question: what does it mean to ask, “What is the meaning of Being?” These questions lie behind the obviousness of everyday life and, therefore, also behind the empirical questions of natural science. They are usually overlooked, because they are too near to everyday life to be grasped. One might say that Heidegger's entire prophetic mission amounts to making each person ask this question with maximum involvement. Whether one arrives at a definite answer is, in the present crisis of mankind, of secondary importance.

      This crisis, according to Heidegger, stems from the deep “fall” (Verfall) of Western thought since the time of Plato, a condition brought about by the one-sided development of technological thinking and the neglect of other kinds, resulting in alienation (Entfremdung)—or, as expressed in terms more central to Heidegger's thought, in a “highly inauthentic way of being.” Although fallenness, or inauthenticity, is an inescapable feature of human existence—i.e., it is an existential, and an essential, potentiality (Möglichkeit)—epochs and individuals may be coloured by it in different degrees. This somewhat stern outlook was mitigated in Heidegger's later writings, in which he suggested that it is possible to find a kind of “redemption” through “thinking of Being”—a process that would be led, he believed, by the continental European countries rather than the eastern or other western ones.

      As an aid in the effort to get back to “thinking of Being” and its redemptive effects, Heidegger employs linguistic (language), or hermeneutical, techniques. He develops his own German, his own Greek, and his own etymologies—for example, he coins about 100 new complex words ending with “-being.” In reading his works one must, therefore, translate many key terms back into Greek and then consider his free, often special (but never uninteresting) interpretations and etymologies.

      The wealth of ideas in Being and Time is best discussed in conjunction with those developed in another, shorter work, What Is Metaphysics? (1929), which was originally delivered as an inaugural lecture when Heidegger succeeded Husserl at Freiburg in 1928. As Heidegger learned from Husserl, it is the phenomenological and not the scientific method that unveils man's ways of Being. Thus, in pursuing this method, Heidegger comes into conflict with the dichotomy of the subject-object relation, which has traditionally implied that man, as knower, is something (some-thing) within an environment that is against him. This relation, however, must be transcended. The deepest knowing, on the contrary, is a matter of phainesthai (Greek: “to show itself” or “to be in the light”), the word from which phenomenology, as a method, is derived. Something is just “there” in the light. Thus, the distinction between subject and object is not immediate but comes only later through conceptualization, as in the sciences.

      Man stands out from things (ex-sists, not merely ex-ists), says Heidegger in Being and Time, never being completely absorbed by them but nevertheless being nothing (no-thing) apart from them. Man dwells in a world that he has been, and continues to be, “thrown into” until death. Being thrown into things, being-there (Da-sein), he falls away (Verfall) and is on the point of being submerged into things. He is continually a pro-ject (Ent-wurf); but periodically, or even normally, he may be submerged in things to such a degree that he is temporarily absorbed (Aufgehen in). He is then nobody in particular; and a structure that Heidegger calls das Man (“the they”) is revealed, recalling certain Anglo-American sociological criticisms of modern industrial society that stress man's “other-directedness”—i.e., his tendency to measure himself in terms of his peers. But Heidegger's phenomenological metaphors avoid the concepts of social science as much as possible in favour of the concepts of ontology. Characteristic of das Man are idle talk (Gerede) and curiosity (Neugier). In Gerede, talker and listener do not stand in any genuine personal relation or in any intimate relation to what is talked about; hence, it leads to shallowness. Curiosity is a form of distraction, a need for the “new,” a need for something “different,” without real interest or capability of wonder.

      But there is a mood, anxiety or dread (Angst), that functions to disclose (dis-close) authentic being, freedom (Frei-sein), as a potentiality. It manifests the freedom of man to choose himself and take hold of himself. The relevance of time, of the finiteness of human existence, is then experienced as a freedom to meet one's own death (das Freisein für den Tod), as a preparedness for and a continuous relatedness to death (Sein zum Tode). In anxiety, all entities (Seiendes) sink away into a “nothing and nowhere,” and man hovers in himself as ex-sisting, being nowhere at home (Un-heimlichkeit, Un-zu-hause). He faces no-thing-ness (das Nichts); and all average, obvious everydayness disappears—and this is good, since he now faces the potentiality of authentic being.

      Thus, for Heidegger the “sober” (nüchtern) anxiety and the implied confrontation with death are primarily of methodological importance, because through them fundamental structures are revealed. Among them are potentialities for being joyfully active (“. . . knowing joy [die wissende Heiterkeit] is a door to the eternal”). Anxiety opens man up to Being. This does not imply that Being partakes in the dark aspect of dread, however; Being is associated with “light” and with “the joyful” (das Heitere). Being “calls the tune”; “to think Being” is to arrive at one's (true) home. Although Heideggerian students are often baffled by just what Being and Thinking stand for, it is clear that Heidegger opposes a cult of mankind and wishes to call attention to something greater.

      In the early 1930s Heidegger's thought underwent a change that scholars call his Kehre (“turning around”). Although some specialists regard the Kehre as a turning away from the central problem of Being and Time, Heidegger himself denied this, insisting that he had been asking the same basic question since his youth. Nevertheless, in his later years he clearly became more reluctant to offer an answer, or even to indicate a way in which an answer might be found.

Heidegger and Nazism (National Socialism)
      In the months after the appointment of Adolf Hitler (Hitler, Adolf) as chancellor of Germany in January 1933, German universities came under increasing pressure to support the “national revolution” and to eliminate Jewish scholars and the teaching of “Jewish” doctrines, such as the theory of relativity. After the rector of Freiburg resigned to protest these policies, the university's teaching staff elected Heidegger as his successor in April 1933. One month later, Heidegger became a member of the Nazi Party, and until he resigned as rector in April 1934 he helped to institute Nazi educational and cultural programs at Freiburg and vigorously promoted the domestic and foreign policies of the Nazi regime. Already during the late 1920s he had criticized the dissolute nature of the German university system, where “specialization” and the ideology of “academic freedom” precluded the attainment of a higher unity. In a letter of 1929, he bemoaned the progressive “Jewification” (Verjudung) of the German spirit. In his inaugural address, Die Selbstbehauptung der deutschen Universität (“The Self-Assertion of the German University”), he called for reorganizing the university along the lines of the Nazi Führerprinzip, or leadership principle, and celebrated the fact that university life would henceforward be merged with the state and the needs of the German Volk. During the first month of his rectorship, he sent a telegram to Hitler urging him to postpone an upcoming meeting of university rectors until Gleichschaltung—the Nazi euphemism for the elimination of political opponents—had been completed. In the fall of 1933, Heidegger began a speaking tour on behalf of Hitler's national referendum to withdraw Germany from the League of Nations (Nations, League of). As he proclaimed in one speech: “Let not doctrines and ideas be your guide. The Führer is Germany's only reality and law.” Heidegger continued to support Hitler in the years after his rectorship, though with somewhat less enthusiasm than he had shown in 1933–34.

      At the end of the war in 1945, a favourably disposed university de-Nazification commission found Heidegger guilty of having “consciously placed the great prestige of his scholarly reputation … in the service of the National Socialist Revolution,” and he was banned from further teaching. (The ban was lifted in 1950.) In later years, despite pleas from friends and associates to disavow publicly his Nazi past, Heidegger declined to do so. Instead, in his own defense, he preferred to cite a maxim from the French poet Paul Valéry (Valéry, Paul): “He who thinks greatly must err greatly.” In his book Introduction to Metaphysics, published in 1953, Heidegger retrospectively praised “the inner truth and greatness of National Socialism.”

      Beginning in the 1980s, there was considerable controversy among Heidegger scholars regarding the alleged connection between Heidegger's philosophy and his political views in the 1930s and '40s. Were there affinities between Heidegger's philosophical thought, or his style of philosophizing, and the totalitarian ideals of the Nazis? Supporters of Heidegger, repeating a view prominent in the first decades after the war, argued that there was nothing inherently fascistic in his philosophy and that claims to the contrary grossly distorted his work. Opponents, on the other hand, cited parallels between the critical treatment in Being and Time of notions such as “publicness,” “everydayness,” “idle talk,” and “curiosity” and fascist-oriented critiques of the vapidity and dissoluteness of bourgeois liberalism. They also pointed to more specific similarities evident in Division II of Being and Time, in which Heidegger emphasizes the centrality of the Volk as a historical actor and the importance of “choosing a hero,” an idea widely promoted among the German right as the Führerprinzip. For these scholars, Heidegger's philosophical critique of the condition of man in modern technological society allowed him to regard the Nazi revolution as a deliverance that would make the world “safe for Being.” Among those who shared this view were the German existentialist philosopher Karl Jaspers (Jaspers, Karl), who wrote in a letter to the head of the de-Nazification commission that “Heidegger's manner of thinking, which to me seems in its essence unfree, dictatorial, and incapable of communication, would today be disastrous in its pedagogical effects.”

Assessment
      Heidegger's thought has been faulted on other grounds as well. Some have suggested that his phenomenological method rests on a grandiose illusion, and that the search for “thinking Being” is merely a disguised quest for a kind of belief in God. In the same vein, others have charged that Heidegger's abstruse terminology is only a mask disguising and mystifying a more traditional approach to philosophy. Such negative evaluations, if joined with a sincere attempt to follow Heidegger's own path through his writings, would not be incompatible with his thought. After all, he asks—or rather, provokes—his readers to question, not to listen to answers. It is, therefore, misleading to present Heidegger's philosophy as a set of clearly understandable results. His metaphors must remain, rather than be translated into the usual philosophical terminology that he rejected.

Arne D. Naess Richard Wolin

Major Works
“Das Realitätsproblem in der modernen Philosophie,” Philosophisches Jahrbuch, 25(3):353–363 (1912); Die Lehre vom Urteil im Psychologismus: Ein kritisch-positiver Beitrag zur Logik (1914); Die Kategorien- und Bedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus (1916); “Der Zeitbegriff in der Geschichtswissenschaft,” Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik, 161(2):173–188 (1916); Sein und Zeit, first as a contribution to the Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 8:1–438 (1927), then as a separate book (1927; Being and Time, 1962); Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (1929; Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, 1962); Vom Wesen des Grundes (1929; The Essence of Reasons, 1969); Was ist Metaphysik? (1929; “What Is Metaphysics?,” in the selective volume Existence and Being, ed. by Werner Brock, 1949, pp. 325–361); Die Selbstbehauptung der deutschen Universität (address of 1933, published 1934); Hölderlin und das Wesen der Dichtung (lecture of 1936, published 1937; “Hölderlin and the Essence of Poetry,” in Existence and Being, pp. 270–291); Platons Lehre von der Wahrheit, first as a contribution to Geistige Überlieferung, 2:96–124 (1942), then in book form (1947; John Barlow [trans.], “Plato's Doctrine of Truth,” in vol. 3 of Philosophy in the Twentieth Century, ed. by William Barrett and Henry D. Aiken [1962], pp. 251–270); Vom Wesen der Wahrheit (lecture of 1930, published 1943; “On the Essence of Truth,” in Existence and Being, pp. 292–324); Erläuterungen zu Hölderlins Dichtung (1944; 4th ed., 1971; Elucidations of Hölderlin's Poetry, 2000); Brief über den “Humanismus,” in Platons Lehre von der Wahrheit (1947); Holzwege (1950); Einführung in die Metaphysik (1953; 5th rev. ed., 1987; An Introduction to Metaphysics, 1959); Der Feldweg (1953); Vorträge und Aufsätze (1954); Was heisst Denken? (1954; What Is Called Thinking?, 1968); Aus der Erfahrung des Denkens (1954; expanded in Aus der Erfahrung des Denkens, 1910–1976, 1983); Was ist das—die Philosophie? (1956; What Is Philosophy?, 1956); Zur Seinsfrage (1956; The Question of Being, 1956); Der Satz vom Grund (1957; The Principle of Reason, 1991); Identität und Differenz (1957; Essays in Metaphysics: Identity and Difference, 1960); Unterwegs zur Sprache (1959; On the Way to Language, 1971); Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes (lecture of 1935, later published in Holzwege [1950]; “The Origin of the Work of Art” in Albert Hofstadter and Richard Kuhns [eds.], Philosophies of Art and Beauty: Selected Readings in Aesthetics from Plato to Heidegger [1964], pp. 649–701); Nietzsche, 2 vol. (1961; Nietzsche, trans. by David Farrell Krell, 4 vol., 1979–87); Die Frage nach dem Ding: zu Kants Lehre von den transzendentalen Grundsätzen (1962; What Is a Thing?, 1967); Kants These über das Sein, first as a lecture (1961), then in Thomas Würtenberger (ed.), Existenz und Ordnung (1962), then as a separate book (1963).

Additional Reading
Hans Albert, Traktat über kritische Vernunft, 5th rev. and enlarged ed. (1991), is a critique of Heidegger's conception of cognition as revelation. Hildegard Feick, Index zu Heideggers “Sein und Zeit,” 4th rev. ed., edited by Susanne Ziegler (1991), is a useful collection of definitions and a survey of occurrences of key terms. Marjorie Grene, “Heidegger, Martin,” in Paul Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 3 (1967), pp. 459–465, is an attempted translation and survey of Heideggerian concepts. Hermann Lübbe, “Bibliographie der Heidegger-Litteratur 1917–1955,” Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung, vol. 11, part 3, pp. 401–452 (July–September 1957), is excellent. G. Lukács, “Heidegger redivivus,” in Sinn und Form, 1:37–62 (1949), is an important Marxist evaluation of the work and influence of Heidegger. Also useful are John Macquarrie, An Existentialist Theology: A Comparison of Heidegger and Bultmann (1955, reprinted 1979); Arne Naess, “Martin Heidegger,” in Four Modern Philosophers: Carnap, Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Sartre (1968; originally published in Swedish, 1965), pp. 173–264; Otto Pöggeler, Martin Heidegger's Path of Thinking (1987, reissued 1989; originally published in German, 1963), and Philosophie und Politik bei Heidegger, 2nd expanded ed. (1974); George Steiner, Heidegger, 2nd ed., rev. and expanded (1992; also published as Martin Heidegger, 1979, reissued 1991); Paul A. Bové, Destructive Poetics: Heidegger and Modern American Poetry (1980); Steven L. Bindeman, Heidegger and Wittgenstein: The Poetics of Silence (1981); Henry G. Wolz, Plato and Heidegger: In Search of Selfhood (1981); and David R. Mason, Time and Providence: An Essay Based on an Analysis of the Concept of Time in Whitehead and Heidegger (1982). Heidegger's involvement with Nazism is discussed in Hugo Ott, Martin Heidegger: A Political Life (1993; originally published in German, 1988); Richard Wolin (ed.), The Heidegger Controversy: A Critical Reader (1991, reissued 1993); and Johannes Fritsche, Historical Destiny and National Socialism in Heidegger's “Being and Time” (1999).Arne D. Naess Richard Wolin

* * *


Universalium. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать реферат

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Heidegger, Martin — (1889 1976)    Among the most revered and controversial of modern philosophers, the German existentialist Martin Heidegger spent his career exploring the meaning of Being. While Leibniz believed the fundamental question was Why is there something …   Christian Philosophy

  • Heidegger, Martin — (1889–1976)    Philosopher.    Heidegger was born in Messkirch, Germany, and was educated at the University of Freiberg. In 1923 he began his teaching career at Marburg, where he was a colleague of Paul tillich and Rudolf bultmann and in 1929 he… …   Who’s Who in Christianity

  • Heidegger, Martin — (1889–1976) German existentialist and social critic. Heidegger is probably the most divisive philosopher of the 20th century, being an acknowledged leader and central figure to many (‘continental’) philosophers, and either a convenient example of …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Heidegger, Martin — (1889 1976)    philosopher; widely judged the cen tral figure in twentieth century existentialist thought. Born to a Catholic* sexton in the Baden town of Messkirch, he was a Jesuit novice before studying theology at Freiburg. Attracted by the… …   Historical dictionary of Weimar Republik

  • Heidegger, Martin — ► (1889 1976) Filósofo alemán, su pensamiento tuvo larga hegemonía en la República Federal Alemana. Iniciado en el análisis estructural husserliano de la conciencia pura, y compartiendo la tendencia fenomenológica a la descripción metódica de las …   Enciclopedia Universal

  • HEIDEGGER, Martin — (1884 1976)    a central figure in contemporary continental PHILOSOPHY, the development of EXISTENTIALISM and new directions in HERMENEUTICS. In Being and Time (1927) he characterized everyday existence as unauthentic because we are thrown into… …   Concise dictionary of Religion

  • Heidegger,Martin — Hei·deg·ger (hīʹdĕg ər, dĭ gər), Martin. 1889 1976. German existentialist philosopher. His masterpiece, Being and Time (1927), argued that confronting the question of the meaning of being, encompassing one s own death, was central for an… …   Universalium

  • Heidegger, Martin — See Existence (Philosophy of) 1 …   History of philosophy

  • Heidegger, Martin — (1889 1976) A German existentialist philosopher, who adopted Edmund Husserl s phenomenological method, in order to investigate the nature of human existence. His most significant work is Being and Time (1926), which was an important influence on… …   Dictionary of sociology

  • Heidegger, Martin —  (1889–1976) German philosopher …   Bryson’s dictionary for writers and editors

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”