rationalism

rationalism
rationalist, n.rationalistic, rationalistical, adj.rationalistically, adv.
/rash"euh nl iz'euhm/, n.
1. the principle or habit of accepting reason as the supreme authority in matters of opinion, belief, or conduct.
2. Philos.
a. the doctrine that reason alone is a source of knowledge and is independent of experience.
b. (in the philosophies of Descartes, Spinoza, etc.) the doctrine that all knowledge is expressible in self-evident propositions or their consequences.
3. Theol. the doctrine that human reason, unaided by divine revelation, is an adequate or the sole guide to all attainable religious truth.
4. Archit. (often cap.)
a. a design movement principally of the mid-19th century that emphasized the development of modern ornament integrated with structure and the decorative use of materials and textures rather than as added adornment.
b. the doctrines and practices of this movement. Cf. functionalism (def. 1).
[1790-1800; RATIONAL + -ISM]

* * *

Philosophical view that regards reason as the chief source and test of knowledge.

Rationalism has long been the rival of empiricism, the doctrine that all knowledge of matters of fact ultimately derives from, and must be tested by, sense experience. As against this doctrine, rationalism holds reason to be a faculty that can lay hold of truths beyond the reach of sense perception, both in certainty and in generality. In stressing the existence of a "natural light," rationalism also has been the rival of systems claiming esoteric knowledge, whether from mystical experience, revelation, or intuition, and has been opposed to various irrationalisms that tend to stress the biological, the emotional or volitional, the unconscious, or the existential at the expense of the rational.

* * *

Introduction

      the philosophical view that regards reason as the chief source and test of knowledge (epistemology). Holding that reality itself has an inherently logical (logic) structure, the Rationalist asserts that a class of truths exists that the intellect can grasp directly. There are, according to the Rationalists, certain rational principles—especially in logic and mathematics (mathematics, philosophy of), and even in ethics and metaphysics—that are so fundamental that to deny them is to fall into contradiction. The Rationalist's confidence in reason and proof tends, therefore, to detract from his respect for other ways of knowing.

      Rationalism has long been the rival of Empiricism, the doctrine that all knowledge comes from, and must be tested by, sense experience. As against this doctrine, Rationalism holds reason to be a faculty that can lay hold of truths beyond the reach of sense perception, both in certainty and generality. In stressing the existence of a “natural light,” Rationalism has also been the rival of systems claiming esoteric knowledge, whether from mystical experience, revelation, or intuition, and has been opposed to various irrationalisms that tend to stress the biological, the emotional or volitional, the unconscious, or the existential at the expense of the rational.

Types and expressions of Rationalism
      Rationalism has somewhat different meanings in different fields, depending upon the kind of theory to which it is opposed.

      In the psychology of perception, for example, Rationalism is in a sense opposed to the genetic psychology of the Swiss scholar Jean Piaget, who, exploring the development of thought and behaviour in the infant, argued that the categories of the mind develop only through the infant's experience in concourse with the world. Similarly, Rationalism is opposed to Transactionalism, a point of view in psychology according to which man's perceptual skills are achievements, accomplished through actions performed in response to an active environment. On this view, the experimental claim is made that perception is conditioned by probability judgments formed on the basis of earlier actions performed in similar situations. As a corrective to these sweeping claims, the Rationalist defends a nativism, which holds that certain perceptual and conceptual capacities are innate (innate idea)—as suggested in the case of depth perception by experiments with “the visual cliff,” which, though platformed over with firm glass, the infant perceives as hazardous—though these native capacities may, at times, lie dormant until the appropriate conditions for their emergence arise.

 In the comparative study of languages (linguistics), a similar nativism was developed in the 1950s by the innovating syntactician Noam Chomsky (Chomsky, Noam), who, acknowledging a debt to Descartes (Descartes, René), explicitly accepted the rationalistic doctrine of “innate ideas.” Though the 4,000 languages spoken in the world differ greatly in sounds and symbols, they sufficiently resemble each other in syntax to suggest that there is “a schema of universal grammar” determined by “deep structures” or “innate presettings” in the human mind itself. These presettings, which have their basis in the brain, set the pattern for all experience, fix the rules for the formation of meaningful sentences, and explain why languages are readily translatable into one another. It should be added that what Rationalists have held about innate ideas is not that some ideas are full-fledged at birth but only that the grasp of certain connections and self-evident principles, when it comes, is due to inborn powers of insight rather than to learning by experience.

      Common to all forms of speculative Rationalism is the belief that the world is a rationally ordered whole, the parts of which are linked by logical necessity and the structure of which is therefore intelligible. Thus in metaphysics it is opposed to the view that reality is a disjointed aggregate of incoherent bits and is thus opaque to reason. In particular, it is opposed to the logical atomisms (Logical Atomism) of such thinkers as David Hume (Hume, David) and Ludwig Wittgenstein (Wittgenstein, Ludwig), who held that facts are so disconnected that any fact might well have been different from what it is without entailing a change in any other fact. Rationalists have differed, however, with regard to the closeness and completeness with which the facts are bound together. At the lowest level, they have all believed that the law of contradiction “A and not-A cannot coexist” holds for the real world, which means that every truth is consistent with every other; at the highest level, they have held that all facts go beyond consistency to a positive coherence; i.e., they are so bound up with each other that none could be different without all being different.

      In the field where its claims are clearest—in epistemology, or theory of knowledge—Rationalism holds that some, at least, of man's knowledge is gained through a priori (a priori knowledge) (prior to experience), or rational, insight as distinct from sense experience, which too often provides a confused and merely tentative approach. In the debate between Empiricism and Rationalism, Empiricists hold the simpler and more sweeping position, the Humean claim that all knowledge of fact stems from perception. Rationalists, on the contrary, urge that some, though not all, knowledge arises through direct apprehension by the intellect. What the intellectual faculty apprehends is objects that transcend sense experience—universals and their relations. A universal is an abstraction, a characteristic that may reappear in various instances: the number three, for example, or the triangularity that all triangles have in common. Though these cannot be seen, heard, or felt, Rationalists point out that man can plainly think about them and about their relations. This kind of knowledge, which includes the whole of logic and mathematics as well as fragmentary insights in many other fields, is, in the Rationalist view, the most important and certain knowledge that the mind can achieve. Such a priori knowledge is both necessary (i.e., it cannot be conceived as otherwise) and universal, in the sense that it admits of no exceptions. In critical philosophy, epistemological Rationalism finds expression in the claim that the mind imposes its own inherent categories or forms upon incipient experience (see below Epistemological Rationalism in modern philosophies (Rationalism)).

      In ethics Rationalism holds the position that reason, rather than feeling, custom, or authority, is the ultimate court of appeal in judging good and bad, right and wrong (categorical imperative). Among major thinkers, the most notable representative of rational ethics is Immanuel Kant (Kant, Immanuel), who held that the way to judge an act is to check its self-consistency as apprehended by the intellect: to note, first, what it is essentially, or in principle—a lie, for example, or a theft—and then to ask if one can consistently will that the principle be made universal. Is theft, then, right? The answer must be “No,” because, if theft were generally approved, no one's property would be his own as opposed to anyone else's and theft would then become meaningless; the notion, if universalized, would thus destroy itself, as reason, by itself, is sufficient to show.

      In religion (religion, philosophy of) Rationalism commonly means that all of man's knowledge comes through the use of his natural faculties, without the aid of supernatural revelation. “Reason” is here used in a broader sense, referring to man's cognitive powers generally, as opposed to supernatural grace or faith—though it is also in sharp contrast to so-called existential approaches to truth. Reason, for the Rationalist, thus stands opposed to many of the religions of the world, including Christianity, which have held that the divine has revealed itself through inspired persons or writings and which have required, at times, that its claims be accepted as infallible, even when they do not accord with natural knowledge. Religious Rationalists hold, on the other hand, that if the clear insights of man's reason must be set aside in favour of alleged revelation, then human thought is everywhere rendered suspect—even in the reasonings of the theologians themselves. There cannot be two ultimately different ways of warranting truth, they assert; hence Rationalism urges that reason, with its standard of consistency, must be the final court of appeal. Religious Rationalism can reflect either a traditional piety, when endeavouring to display the alleged sweet reasonableness of religion, or an anti-authoritarian temper, when aiming to supplant religion with the “goddess of reason.”

History of Rationalism

Epistemological Rationalism in ancient philosophies
      The first Western philosopher to stress rationalist insight was Pythagoras, a shadowy figure of the 6th century BC. Noticing that, for a right triangle, a square built on its hypotenuse equals the sum of those on its sides and that the pitches of notes sounded on a lute bear a mathematical relation to the lengths of the strings, Pythagoras held that these harmonies reflected the ultimate nature of reality. He summed up the implied metaphysical Rationalism in the words “All is number.” It is probable that he had caught the Rationalist's vision, later seen by Galileo, of a world governed throughout by mathematically formulable laws.

      The difficulty in this view, however, is that, working with universals and their relations, which, like the multiplication table, are timeless and changeless, it assumes a static world and ignores the particular, changing things of daily life. The difficulty was met boldly by the Rationalist Parmenides, who insisted that the world really is a static whole and that the realm of change and motion is an illusion, or even a self-contradiction. His disciple Zeno Of Elea further argued that anything thought to be moving is confronted with a row of points infinite in number, all of which it must traverse; hence it can never reach its goal, nor indeed move at all. Of course, perception tells us that we do move; but Zeno, compelled to choose between perception and reason, clung to reason.

 The exalting of rational insight above perception was also prominent in Plato (c. 427–347 BC). In the Meno, Socrates dramatized the innateness of knowledge by calling upon an illiterate slave boy and, drawing a square in the sand, proceeding to elicit from him, step by step, the proof of a theorem in geometry of which the boy could never have heard (to double the size of a square, draw a square on the diagonal). Such knowledge, Rationalists insist, is certain, universal, and completely unlearned.

      Plato so greatly admired the rigorous reasoning of geometry that he is alleged to have inscribed over the door of his Academy “Let no one unacquainted with geometry enter here.” His famous “ideas” are accessible only to reason, not to sense. But how are they related to sensible things? His answers differed. Sometimes he viewed the ideas as distilling those common properties of a class in virtue of which one identifies anything as a member of it. Thus what makes anything a triangle is its having three straight sides; this is its essence. At other times, Plato held that the idea is an ideal, a non-sensible goal to which the sensible thing approximates; the geometer's perfect triangle “never was on sea or land,” though all actual triangles more or less embody it. He conceived the ideas as more real than the sensible things that are their shadows and saw that the philosopher must penetrate to these invisible essences and see with the eye of his mind how they are linked together. For Plato they formed an orderly system that was at once eternal, intelligible, and good.

 Plato's successor Aristotle (384–322 BC) conceived of the work of reason in much the same way, though he did not view the ideas as independent. His chief contribution to Rationalism lay in his syllogistic (syllogism) logic, regarded as the chief instrument of rational explanation. Man explains particular facts by bringing them under general principles. Why does one think Socrates will die? Because he is a man, and man as such is mortal. Why should one accept the general principle itself that all men are mortal? In human experience such principles have so far held without exception. But the mind cannot finally rest in this sort of explanation. Man never wholly understands a fact or event until he can bring it under a principle that is self-evident and necessary; and he then has the clearest explanation possible. On this central thesis of Rationalism, the three great Greeks were in accord.

      Nothing comparable in importance to their thought appeared in Rationalistic philosophy in the next 1,800 years, though the work of Thomas Aquinas (Aquinas, Thomas, Saint) in the 13th century was an impressive attempt to blend Greek Rationalism and Christian revelation into a single harmonious system.

      Thoroughgoing Rationalism is to be found only in the philosophical tradition that has come down from Greece; the mysticism of India and the practicality of China have offered a less congenial soil for it. The nearest parallels to it in Eastern thought are found in the work of the Indian philosopher Śaṅkara, who flourished about AD 800, and in that of the Chinese sage Chu-Hsi (Zhu Xi) (1130–1200). Both were commentators on the ancient scriptures of their lands; and in ordering the scattered insights of these sources into intelligible systems, they did for their respective peoples something like what Aquinas did for the West in his harmonizing of Greek with Christian thought. Śaṅkara held, as Sir Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan has expressed it, that “the Absolute is the unattainable goal towards which the finite intellect strives.” Perception is confined to what is transient and fragmentary; reason rises to truth that is timeless and universal; but even reason falls short of full understanding, which is achieved, if at all, only through mystical vision. Chu Hsi, who has influenced Chinese thought for the past six centuries, was a disciple of Confucius, though he had a stronger speculative interest than his master. He held that in all human minds a single reason was at work, which he called “the Way.” All things were in some degree manifestations of it, and hence the understanding of the world lay in more complete identification with it.

Epistemological Rationalism in modern philosophies
 The first modern Rationalist was René Descartes (1596–1650), who was an original mathematician whose ambition was to introduce into philosophy the rigour and clearness that delighted him in mathematics. He set out to doubt (methodic doubt) everything in the hope of arriving in the end at something indubitable. This he reached in his famous cogito ergo sum (cogito, ergo sum), “I think, therefore I am”; for to doubt one's own doubting would be absurd. Here then was a fact of absolute certainty, rendered such by the clearness and distinctness with which it presented itself to his reason. His task was to build on this as a foundation, to deduce from it a series of other propositions, each following with the same self-evidence. He hoped thus to produce a philosophical system on which men could agree as completely as they do on the geometry of Euclid. The main cause of error, he held, lay in the impulsive desire to believe before the mind is clear. The clearness and distinctness upon which he insisted was not that of perception but of conception, the (concept formation) clearness with which the intellect grasps an abstract idea, such as the number three, or its being greater than two.

      His method was adopted in essentials by both Benedict Spinoza (Spinoza, Benedict de) (1632–77) and G.W. Leibniz (Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm) (1646–1716), who agreed that the framework of things could be known by a priori thinking. They differed from him, however, in their starting points. What was most undeniable to Spinoza was not the existence of his self but that of the universe, called by him Substance. From the idea of Substance, and with the aid of a few definitions and axioms, he derived his entire system, which he set forth in his Ethics in a formal fashion patterned after Euclid's geometry. Still, for both Spinoza and Leibniz much in nature remained stubbornly opaque. Leibniz distinguished necessary truths, those of which the opposite is impossible (as in mathematics), from contingent truths, the opposite of which is possible, such as “snow is white.” But was this an ultimate distinction? At times Leibniz said boldly that if only man knew enough, he would see that every true proposition was necessarily true—that there are no contingent truths, that snow must be white.

 How, then, does reason operate and how is it possible to have knowledge that goes beyond experience? A new answer was given by Immanuel Kant (Kant, Immanuel) (1724–1804) in his Critique of Pure Reason, which, as he said, involved a Copernican revolution in philosophy. The reason man can be certain that his logic and mathematics will remain valid for all experience is simply that their framework lies within his own mind; they are forms of arrangement imposed from within upon the raw materials of sensation. Man will always find things arranged in certain patterns because it is he who has unwittingly so arranged them. Kant held, however, that these certainties were bought at a heavy price. Just because a priori insights are the reflection of man's own mind, he cannot trust them as a reflection of the world outside himself. Whether the rational order in which man arranges his sensation—the order, for example, of time, space, and causality—represents an order holding among things-in-themselves (German Dinge-an-sich) he cannot hope to know. Kant's Rationalism was thus the counterpart of a profound Skepticism.

 G.W.F. Hegel (Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich) (1770–1831), the most thoroughgoing of Rationalist thinkers, attempted to break out of this Skepticism. He argued that to think of an unknowable is already to bring it within the sphere of what is known and that it is meaningless to talk of a region in which logic is invalid. Further, to raise the question “Why?” is to presume that there is an intelligible answer to it; indeed the faith of the philosopher must be that the real is the rational and the rational real, for this faith is implicit in the philosophic enterprise itself. As an attempt to understand and explain the world, philosophy is a process of placing something in a context that reveals it as necessary. But this necessity is not, as earlier Rationalists had supposed, an all-or-nothing affair issuing in a self-evident finality. Understanding is a matter of degree. What alone would wholly satisfy thought is a system that is at once all-inclusive and so ordered that its parts entail each other. Hegel believed that the universe constitutes such a whole and, as an idealist, held that it is a single, absolute (Absolute Idealism) mind. To the degree that the philosopher embodies and realizes this mind, his own mind will achieve both truth and reality. Indeed, the advance of civilization reflects the enlarging presence and control of such a system in the human spirit. Broadly similar Rationalistic systems were developed in England by F.H. Bradley (Bradley, F H) (1846–1924) and Bernard Bosanquet (Bosanquet, Bernard) (1848–1923) and in America by Josiah Royce (Royce, Josiah) (1855–1916).

Ethical Rationalism
      The views of Kant were presented above as typical of this position (see above, Types and expressions of Rationalism (Rationalism)). But few moralists have held to ethical Rationalism in this simple and sweeping form. Many have held, however, that the main rules of conduct are truths as self-evident as those of logic or mathematics. Lists of such rules were drawn up by Ralph Cudworth (Cudworth, Ralph) and Henry More (More, Henry) among the Cambridge Platonists of the 17th century, who were noted for holding that moral principles were intrinsic to reality; and in the 18th century Samuel Clarke (Clarke, Samuel) and Richard Price (Price, Richard), defenders of “natural law” ethics, and the “common sense” moralist Thomas Reid (Reid, Thomas) also presented such lists. A 20th-century revision of this Rationalism has been offered by the Rational Intuitionists (intuition) H.A. Prichard (Prichard, H.A.) and Sir David Ross (Ross, Sir David) of Oxford under the name of deontology (deontological ethics) (Greek deon, “duty”), which respects duty more than consequences. Ross provides a list of propositions regarding fidelity to promises, reparation for injuries, and other duties, of which he says: “In our confidence that these propositions are true there is involved the same trust in our reason that is involved in our trust in mathematics.” What is taken as self-evident, however, is not specific rules of conduct, but prima facie duties—the claims that some types of action have on men because of their nature. If a man is considering whether to repay a debt or to give the money to charity, each act has a self-evident claim on him; and their comparative strengths must be settled by a rational intuition.

      The most influential variety of 20th-century ethical Rationalism has probably been the Ideal Utilitarianism of the British moralists Hastings Rashdall (1858–1924) and G.E. Moore (Moore, G E) (1873–1958). Both were teleologists (teleology) (Greek telos, “end”) inasmuch as they held that what makes an act objectively right is its results (or end) in intrinsic goods or evils. To determine what is right, reason is required in two senses: firstly, the inference to the consequences is an act of inductive reasoning; secondly, the judgment that one consequence is intrinsically better than another is a priori and self-evident. Moore thought that there is a single rule for all conduct—one should so act as to produce the greatest good—and that this is also a principle self-evident to reason.

Religious Rationalism
      Stirrings of religious Rationalism were already felt in the Middle Ages regarding the Christian revelation. Thus the skeptical mind of Abelard (Abelard, Peter) (1079–1142) raised doubts by showing in his Sic et Non (“Yes and No”) many contradictions among beliefs handed down as revealed truths by the Church Fathers. The greatest of the Medieval thinkers, Thomas Aquinas (1225–74), was a Rationalist in the sense of believing that the larger part of revealed truth was intelligible to and demonstrable by reason, though he thought that a number of dogmas opaque to reason must be accepted on authority alone.

Expansion of religious Rationalism
      Religious Rationalism did not come into its own, however, until the 16th and 17th centuries, when it took two chief forms: the scientific and the philosophic.

       Galileo (1564–1642) was a pioneer in astronomy and the founder of modern dynamics. He conceived of nature as governed throughout by laws statable with mathematical precision; the book of nature, he said, is “written in mathematical form.” This notion not only ruled out the occasional appeal to miracle; it also collided with dogmas regarding the permanent structure of the world—in particular with that which viewed the Earth as the motionless centre of the universe. When Galileo's demonstration that the Earth moves around the Sun was confirmed by the work of Newton and others, a battle was won that marked a turning point in the history of Rationalism, since it provided a decisive victory in a crucial case of conflict between reason and apparently revealed truth.

      The Rationalism of Descartes, as already shown, was the outcome of philosophic doubt rather than of scientific inquiry. The self-evidence of the cogito, (cogito, ergo sum) seen by his “natural light,” he made the ideal for all other knowledge. The uneasiness that the church soon felt in the face of such a test was not unfounded, for Descartes was in effect exalting the natural light into the supreme court even in the field of religion. He argued that man's guarantee against the possibility that even this natural light might deceive him lay in the goodness of the Creator. But then to prove this Creator, he had to assume the prior validity of the natural light itself. Logically, therefore, the last word lay with rational insight, not with any outside divine warrant. Descartes (Descartes, René) was inadvertently beginning a Copernican revolution in theology. Before his time, the truths regarded as most certain were those accepted from revelation; afterwards these truths were subject to the judgment of human reason, thus breaking the hold of authority on the European mind.

Four waves of religious Rationalism
      The Rationalist attitude quickly spread, its advance forming several waves of general interest and influence. The first wave occurred in England in the form of Deism. Deists accepted the existence of God, but spurned supernatural revelation. The earliest member of this school, Lord Herbert of Cherbury (Herbert, Edward Herbert, 1st Baron) (1583–1648), held that a just God would not reveal himself to a part of his creation only and that the true religion is thus a universal one, which achieves its knowledge of God through common reason. The Deistic philosopher John Toland (Toland, John) (1670–1722), in his Christianity Not Mysterious, sought to show that “there is nothing in the Gospels contrary to reason, nor above it”; any doctrine that is really above reason would be meaningless to man. Attacking revelation, the freethinking polemicist Anthony Collins (Collins, Anthony) (1676–1729) maintained that the prophecies of the Old Testament failed of fulfillment; and the religious controversialist Thomas Woolston (Woolston, Thomas) (1670–1733) urged that the New Testament miracles, as recorded, are incredible. Matthew Tindal (1657–1733), most learned of the English Deists, argued that the essential part of Christianity is its ethics, which, being clearly apparent to natural reason, leaves revelation superfluous. Thus the Deists, professing for the most part to be religious men themselves, did much to reconcile their public to the free play of ideas in religion.

 The second wave of religious Rationalism, less moderate in tone and consequences, was French. This wave, reflecting an engagement with the problem of natural evil (evil, problem of), involved a decay in the natural theology of Deism such that it merged eventually with the stream that led to materialistic atheism. Its moving spirit was Voltaire (1694–1778), who had been impressed by some of the Deists during a stay in England. Like them, he thought that a rational man would believe in God but not in supernatural inspiration. Hardly a profound philosopher, he was a brilliant journalist, clever and humorous in argument, devastating in satire, and warm in human sympathies. In his Candide and in many other writings, he poured irreverent ridicule on the Christian scheme of salvation as incoherent and on the church hierarchy as cruel and oppressive. In these attitudes he had the support of Diderot (Diderot, Denis) (1713–84), editor of the most widely read encyclopaedia that had appeared in Europe. The Rationalism of these men and their followers, directed against both the religious and the political traditions of their time, did much to prepare the ground for the explosive French Revolution.

      The next wave of religious Rationalism occurred in Germany under the influence of Hegel (Hegelianism), who held that a religious creed is a halfway house on the road to a mature philosophy, the product of a reason that is still under the sway of feeling and imagination. This idea was taken up and applied with learning and acuteness to the origins of Christianity by David Friedrich Strauss (Strauss, David Friedrich) (1808–74), who published in 1835, at the age of 27, a remarkable and influential three-volume work, Das Leben Jesu (The Life of Jesus, Critically Examined, 1846). Relying largely on internal inconsistencies in the Synoptic Gospels, Strauss undertook to prove these books to be unacceptable as revelation and unsatisfactory as history. He then sought to show how an imaginative people innocent of either history or science, convinced that a Messiah would appear, and deeply moved by a unique moral genius, inevitably wove myths about his birth and death, his miracles, and his divine communings.

      Strauss's thought as it affected religion was continued by the philosophical historian Ernest Renan (Renan, Ernest) (1823–92) and as it affected philosophy by the humanist Ludwig Feuerbach (Feuerbach, Ludwig) (1804–72) of the Hegelian left. Renan's Vie de Jésus (1863; Life of Jesus) did for France what Strauss's book had done for Germany, though the two differed greatly in character. Whereas Strauss's work had been an intellectual exercise in destructive criticism, Renan's was an attempt to reconstruct the mind of Jesus as a wholly human person—a feat of imagination, performed with a disarming admiration and even reverence for its subject and with a felicity of style that gave it a large and lasting audience. Feuerbach's Wesen des Christentums (1841; Eng. trans. by George Eliot, Essence of Christianity, 1853) applied the myth theory even to belief in the existence of God, holding that “man makes God in his own image.”

      The fourth wave occurred in Victorian England, following the publication in 1859 of Darwin's Origin of Species. This book was taken as a challenge to the authority of Scripture because there was a clear inconsistency between the Genesis account of creation and the biological account of man's slow emergence from lower forms of life. The battle raged with bitterness for several decades but died away as the theory of evolution gained more general acceptance.

Status of Rationalism

      With increasing freedom of thought and wider acceptance of scientific views, Rationalism in religion has lost its novelty and much of its controversial excitement. To the contemporary mind, it is too obvious to warrant debate that reason and revelation cannot both qualify as sources of ultimate truth for, were they to conflict, truth itself would become self-contradictory. Hence theologians have sought accommodation through new interpretative principles that discern different grades of authenticity within the Scriptures and through new views of religious truth, existential rather than cognitive, that turn from propositional dogmas to the explication of lived human existence. Criticism of supernaturalism, however, is still carried on by such societies as the Rationalist Press Association, in Great Britain, and the Humanist Association, in the United States.

Ethical
      Rationalism in ethics has suffered its share of criticism. Regarding its lists of rules—on the keeping of promises, the return of loaned goods, etc.—it has been argued, for example, that if they were specific enough to be useful (as in the rule against lying or stealing), they would tend to have exceptions—which no rule laid down by reason ought to have. On the other hand, if without exceptions, they would often prove to be tautologies (tautology): the rule of justice, for example, that we should give everyone his due would then mean only that we should give him what is justly his. After enduring a period of eclipse, however, during which noncognitive theories of ethics (emotive and existential) and relativism had preempted the field, rationalistic views, which agree in holding that moral standards do not depend upon the varying attitudes of persons or peoples, were receiving renewed attention in the mid-20th century. Prominent among these developments has been the “good-reasons (good-reasons theory)” approach taken by the broadly gauged scholar Stephen Toulmin (Toulmin, Stephen Edelston), by Kurt Baier, and others, which examines the contexts of various moral situations and explores the kinds of justification (ethics) appropriate for each.

Metaphysical
      Typical of the ways of reasoning employed by Rationalists are two approaches taken to the metaphysical doctrine that all things are connected by internal relations: one a logical, the other a causal argument. An internal relation is one that could not be removed without affecting the terms themselves between which the relation holds. The argument runs: Everything is related to everything else at least by the relation “A is different from B.” But difference is itself an internal relation, since the terms could not remain the same if it were removed. Hence everything is so connected with everything else that it could not be what it is unless they were what they are. The appeal to internal relations played an important part in the philosophies of Hegel, F.H. Bradley (Bradley, F H), and A.N. Whitehead (Whitehead, Alfred North) (1861–1947).

      The other line of argument is causal (causation). Every event, it is maintained, is connected with every other, either directly or indirectly. Sir James Jeans (Jeans, Sir James) argued that if the law of gravitation is valid, a man cannot crook his little finger without affecting the fixed stars. Here the causal relation is direct. It can also be shown that seemingly unrelated events are joined indirectly through their common connection with some remote historical event, by a chain of events leading back, for example, to Columbus' discovery of America. But if this had been different, all of its consequences would presumably have been different; thus an indirect and internal relation proves to have been present.

      Many Rationalists have held with Spinoza (Spinoza, Benedict de) that the causal relation is really a logical one—that a causal law, if precisely stated, would reveal a connection in which the character of the cause logically necessitates that of its effect; and if this is true, they maintain, the facts and events of the world must thus compose a single rational and intelligible order.

      In the 20th century, such Rationalism met with a new and unexpected difficulty presented by quantum physics. According to the indeterminacy principle (uncertainty principle), formulated in 1927 by the German physicist Werner Heisenberg (Heisenberg, Werner), it is impossible to discover with precision both the position and the velocity of a moving electron at the same time. This implies that definite causal laws for the behaviour of these particles can never be attained, but only statistical laws governing the behaviour of immense aggregates of them. Causality, and with it the possibility of rational understanding, seemed to be suspended in the subatomic world. Some interpreters of the new physics, however, notably Max Planck, Albert Einstein, and Bertrand Russell, sustained the hopes of the Rationalists by insisting that what was excluded by the indeterminacy principle was not the fact of causality in this realm, but only the precise knowledge of it.

      Indeed, some leaders of 20th-century science took the new developments in physics as on the whole supporting Rationalism. Protons and electrons, they contended, though beyond the reach of the senses, can still be known; and their behaviour, at least in groups, is increasingly found to conform to mathematical law. In 1932, Sir James Jeans, an astrophysicist and popularizer of science, said with a curious echo of Galileo, “the universe (metaphysics) appears to have been designed by a pure mathematician.”

Challenges to epistemological Rationalism
      At first glance the claim of Empiricism that knowledge must come from sense experience seems obvious: how else could one hope to make contact with the world around one? Consequently, Rationalism has been sharply challenged—in the 19th century by the Empiricism of John Stuart Mill (Mill, John Stuart) (1806–73) and in the 20th by that of the Logical Positivists (Logical Positivism). Mill argued that all a priori (a priori knowledge) certainties are illusory: why does man believe, for example, that two straight lines cannot enclose a space? Is it because he sees it as logically necessary? No; it is because he has experienced so long and so unbroken a row of instances of it—a new one whenever he sees the corner of a table or the bordering rays of a light beam—that he has formed the habit of thinking in this way and is now unable to break it. A priori propositions, Mill claimed, are merely empirical statements of very high generality.

      This theory has now been abandoned by most Empiricists themselves. Its implication that such statements as “2 + 2 = 4” are only probably true and may have exceptions has proved quite unconvincing. The Rationalist's rejoinder is that one cannot, no matter how hard one tries, conceive 2 + 2 as making 5; for its equalling 4 is necessary. But a priori knowledge is also universal. Neither of these two characteristics can be accounted for by sense experience. That a crow is black can be perceived, but not that it must be black or that crows will always be black; no run of perceptions, however long, could assure us of such truths. On the other hand, a priori truths can be seen with certainty—that if a figure, for instance, is a plane triangle within a Euclidean space, its angles must and always will equal two right angles.

      Perhaps the most formidable challenge to Rationalism has come in the 20th century from such Logical Positivists as the Oxford Empiricist A.J. Ayer (Ayer, Sir A.J.) (1910–89) and Rudolf Carnap (Carnap, Rudolf) (1891–1970), who had been a central figure in the Vienna Circle, where this movement first arose. Unlike Mill, they accepted a priori knowledge as certain; but they laid down a new challenge—the denial of its philosophic importance. A priori propositions, they said, are (1) linguistic, (2) conventional, and (3) analytic (analytic proposition): (1) They are statements primarily of how one proposes to use words; if one says that “a straight line is the shortest line between two points,” this merely reports one's definition of “straight” and declares one's purpose to use it only of the shortest. (2) Being a definition, such a statement expresses a convention to which there are alternatives; it may be defined in terms of the paths of light rays if one chooses. (3) The statement is analytic in that it merely repeats in its predicate a part or the whole of the subject term and hence tells nothing new; it is not a statement about nature but about meanings only. And since Rationalistic systems depend throughout upon statements of this kind, their importance is illusory.

      To this clear challenge some leading Rationalists have replied as follows: (1) Positivists have confused real with verbal definition. A verbal definition does indeed state what a word means; but a real definition states what an object is, and the thought of a straight line is the thought of an object, not of words. (2) The Positivists have confused conventions in thought with conventions in language. One is free to vary the language in which a proposition is expressed, but not the proposition itself. Start with the concept of a straight line, and there is no alternative to accepting it as the shortest. (3) Some a priori statements are admittedly analytic, but many are not. In “whatever is coloured is extended,” colour and extension are two different concepts of which the first entails the second, but is not identical with it in whole or part. Contemporary Rationalists therefore hold that the a priori has emerged victorious from the Empiricists' efforts to discredit such knowledge and the Positivists' attempts to trivialize it.

Brand Blanshard

Additional Reading
The classic ancient Greek work on Rationalism is Plato, Meno; essential modern works are Descartes, Meditationes de Prima Philosophia . . . (Meditations on First Philosophy); Spinoza, Ethics; Leibniz, Monadologie (Monadology and Other Philosophical Writings); and Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Critique of Pure Reason). Rationalism is epitomized in Hegel, Phänomenologie des Geistes (Phenomenology of Mind); Francis Herbert Bradley, Appearance and Reality.For Rationalism in the theory of knowledge, see Brand Blanshard, Reason and Analysis (1962); George Boas, Rationalism in Greek Philosophy (1961); Ernst Cassirer, Die Philosophie der Aufklärung (1932; Eng. trans., Philosophy of the Enlightenment, 1951); M.R. Cohen, Reason and Nature: An Essay on the Meaning of Scientific Method, 2nd ed. (1953): A.C. Ewing, Idealism: A Critical Survey (1934); H.H. Joachim, The Nature of Truth (1906); A.E. Murphy, The Uses of Reason (1943); H.J. Paton, In Defence of Reason (1951); Bertrand Russell, Problems of Philosophy (1912); W.H. Walsh, Reason and Experience (1947).For Rationalism in metaphysics, see the classics listed above. For two outstanding modern examples, see J.M.E. McTaggart, The Nature of Existence, 2 vol. (1921–27), together with the commentary of C.D. Broad, Examination of McTaggart's Philosophy, 2 vol. (1933–38); and Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality (1929). For Rationalism in ethics, see William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated (1722); and Kant, Die Metaphysik der Sitten (1785; Eng. trans., The Metaphysics of Morals, 1799). For early forms of the appeal to self-evident rules, see Richard Price, A Review of the Principal Questions in Morals (1758). For later types of Rationalism, see G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica (1903); W.D. Ross, The Right and the Good (1930), and Foundations of Ethics (1939); Brian Ellis, Rational Belief System (1979).For Rationalism in religion, excellent standard works are: W.E.H. Lecky, History of the Rise and Influence of the Spirit of Rationalism in Europe, 2 vol. (1865); A.D. White, History of the Warfare of Science with Theology in Christendom, 2 vol. (1910); J.M. Robertson, A Short History of Freethought, Ancient and Modern, 2nd ed., 2 vol. (1906); A.W. Benn, History of English Rationalism in the Nineteenth Century, 2 vol. (1906); J.B. Bury, A History of Freedom of Thought (1913). Sigmund Freud, Die Zukunft einer Illusion (1927; Eng. trans., The Future of an Illusion, 1928), offers a psychoanalytic study of religious belief.

* * *


Universalium. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать реферат
Synonyms:
(of the Scriptures)


Look at other dictionaries:

  • Rationalism — • Term used in an exact sense, to designate a particular moment in the development of Protestant thought in Germany, or in a broader, and more usual, sense to cover the view that the human reason, or understanding, is the sole source and final… …   Catholic encyclopedia

  • raţionalism — RAŢIONALÍSM s.n. 1. Curent în teoria cunoaşterii, care consideră raţiunea ca singurul izvor al cunoaşterii autentice şi certe. 2. Încredere în capacitatea raţiunii de a cunoaşte realitatea. [pr.: ţi o ] – Din fr. rationalisme. Trimis de… …   Dicționar Român

  • Rationalism — Ra tion*al*ism (r[a^]sh [u^]n*al*[i^]z m), n. [Cf. F. rationalisme.] 1. (Theol.) The doctrine or system of those who deduce their religious opinions from reason or the understanding, as distinct from, or opposed to, revelation. [1913 Webster] 2.… …   The Collaborative International Dictionary of English

  • rationalism — index dialectic Burton s Legal Thesaurus. William C. Burton. 2006 …   Law dictionary

  • rationalism — ► NOUN ▪ the practice or principle of basing opinions and actions on reason and knowledge rather than on religious belief or emotional response. DERIVATIVES rationalist noun …   English terms dictionary

  • rationalism — [rash′ən əl iz΄əm] n. [ RATIONAL + ISM] 1. the principle or practice of accepting reason as the only authority in determining one s opinions or course of action 2. Philos. the doctrine that knowledge comes from the intellect in itself without aid …   English World dictionary

  • Rationalism — This article is about the philosophical method, position, theory, or view. For other uses, see Rationalism (disambiguation). In epistemology and in its modern sense, rationalism is any view appealing to reason as a source of knowledge or… …   Wikipedia

  • RATIONALISM —    European modernist architecture of the 1920s and 1930s was defined as a functional style of construction stripped of applied decoration, whereby the intrinsic characteristics of a building s materials were brought to the forefront of its… …   Historical Dictionary of Architecture

  • rationalism —    A general tendency in Islamic thought that emphasizes the primacy of reason or intellect (‘aql) over tradition (naql). Rationalist theologians and philosophers believe that God’s existence, His unity and attributes, the origin and order of the …   Islamic philosophy dictionary

  • Rationalism — a theory or method based on the thesis that human reason can in principle be the source of all knowledge. In the modern period, rationalism was initially championed by René Descartes and spread during the 17th and 18th centuries, primarily in… …   Mini philosophy glossary

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”