theism

theism
theist /thee"ist/, n., adj.theistic, theistical, adj.theistically, adv.
/thee"iz euhm/, n.
1. the belief in one God as the creator and ruler of the universe, without rejection of revelation (distinguished from deism).
2. belief in the existence of a god or gods (opposed to atheism).
[1670-80; THE- + -ISM]

* * *

View that all observable phenomena are dependent on but distinct from one supreme being.

The view usually entails the idea that God is beyond human comprehension, perfect and self-sustained, but also peculiarly involved in the world and its events. Theists seek support for their view in rational argument and appeals to experience. Arguments for God's existence are of four principal types: cosmological, ontological, teleological, or moral. A central issue for theism is reconciling God, usually understood as omnipotent and perfect, with the existence of evil. See also agnosticism, atheism, Deism, monotheism, polytheism, theodicy.

* * *

Introduction

      the view that all limited or finite things are dependent in some way on one supreme or ultimate reality of which one may also speak in personal terms.

      Theism's view of God can be clarified by contrasting it with that of Deism, of pantheism, and of mysticism. Deism closely resembles theism; but for the deist, God is not involved in the world in the same personal way. He has made it, so to speak, or set the laws of it—and to that extent he sustains it in being. But subject to this final and somewhat remote control, God, as the deist sees him, allows the world to continue in its own way. This view simplifies some problems, especially those that arise from the scientific account of the world: one does not have to allow for any factor that cannot be handled and understood in the ordinary way. God is in the shadows or beyond; and, though men may still in some way centre their lives upon him, this calls for no radical adjustment at the human or finite level. The deist proceeds, for most purposes at least, as if there were no God—or only an absent one; and this approach is especially true of man's understanding of the world. This is why deism appealed so much to thinkers in the time of the first triumphs of modern science. They could indeed allow for God, but they had “no need of that hypothesis” in science or in their normal account of things. Religion, being wholly superadded, was significant only in a manner that involved little else in the world or in the way man lives. The theist, on the other hand, questions this view and seeks in various ways (as noted below) to bring man's relation to God into closer involvement with the way he understands himself and the world around him.

      Theism also sharply contrasts with pantheism, which identifies God with all that there is; and with various forms of monism, which regards all finite things as parts, modes, limitations, or appearances of some one ultimate Being, which is all that there is. Some types of absolute Idealism, a philosophy of all-pervading Mind, while regarding every finite thing as comprising some limitation of the one whole of Being, seek also to retain the theistic element in their view of the world; and they do this normally—as in the works of A.E. Taylor, Andrew Pringle-Pattison, or G.F. Stout—by stressing the role of unifying finite centres, such as self-conscious human beings, in the way the universe as a whole functions. But there is no recognition here of the finality of what is technically known as “the distinctness of persons.” The theist, by contrast, considers the world to be quite distinct from its Author or Creator, human life being thus in no sense strictly the life of God, while also making room for a peculiarly intimate involvement of God in the world and in human life.

       mysticism in practice comes close to theism; but mystical thought, and much of its practice, has often involved a repudiation of the proper reality of finite things and sometimes (as in a work by W.T. Stace, Mysticism and Philosophy) tends to dismiss all of the finite manifold or multiplicity of things as some wholly unreal phantasm that has no place in the one undiversified Being, which alone is real. Theism is very far removed from ideas of this kind.

Theism in Western thought

God encountered as person
      The idea that the world, as man understands it in a finite way, is dependent on some reality (sacred) altogether beyond his comprehension, perfect and self-sustained but also peculiarly involved in the world and its events, is presented with exceptional sharpness and discernment in the Old Testament, whence it became a formative influence in Hebrew history and subsequently in Christianity and Islām. Behind the creation stories; behind the patriarchal narratives, like that of Jacob at Bethel (Gen. 28) or wrestling with his strange visitor at Penuel (Gen. 32); and behind the high moments of prophecy, like Isaiah's famous vision in the Temple (Isa. 6), and of moving religious experience in the Psalms, in the Book of Job, and (with remarkable explicitness) in some well-known passages, like the story of Moses at the burning bush (Ex. 3)—behind all of these there lies a sense of some mysterious, all-encompassing reality by which man is also in some way addressed and which he may also venture to address in turn. Moses wished to see God (revelation), to have some explicit sign that could convince the people and establish his own authority; but he was shown, instead, that this is just what he could not have: all that he could be assured of was that God is real and is bound to be—“I am who I am,” he was told. On the other hand, in the throes of this humbling and staggering experience, Moses began to learn also what was expected of him and how his people should live and be led. The God who was so strange and elusive was somehow found to be a God who “talked” to him and with whom people could “walk.” The same seemingly bewildering claim of remoteness, almost to the point of unreality, linked with a compelling explicitness and closeness, is also found in other cultures, as illustrated below. This claim presents the reflective thinker with the twofold problem of theism, viz., how, in the first place, a reality as remote and mysterious as the God of theism—the “wholly other,” in the famous words of the German theologian Rudolf Otto—can be known at all; and, second, how, if it can be known, it can be spoken of in precise and intimate ways and encountered as a person.

The existence of God
      There have been many attempts to establish the existence of one supreme and ultimate Being—whom in religion one speaks of as God—and some of these have been given very precise forms in the course of time.

The influence of Plato and Aristotle
      The pattern for many of these was laid down in ancient Greece by Plato. He taught about God mostly in mythical terms, stressing the goodness of God (as in the Republic and Timaeus) and his care for man (as in the Phaedo); but in the Phaedrus, and much more explicitly in the Laws, he presented a more rigorous argument, based on the fact that things change and are in motion. Not all change comes from outside; some of it is spontaneous and must be due to “soul” and ultimately to a supreme or perfect soul. Whether God so conceived quite gives the traditional theist all that he wants, however, is not certain. For God, in Plato, fashions the world on the pattern of immutable Forms and, above all, on “the Good,” which is “beyond being and knowledge”; i.e., it is transcendent and beyond the grasp of thought. But Plato's combination of the notion of the transcendent, which is also supremely good, and the argument from change, provided the model for much of the course that subsequent philosophical arguments were to take. Aristotle made the argument from motion more precise, but he coupled it with a doubtful astronomical view and a less theistic notion of God, who, as the unmoved mover, is the ultimate source of all other movement, not by expressly communicating it but by being a supreme object of aspiration, all appetite and activity being in fact directed to some good. Aristotle thus set the pattern for the more deistic view of God, whereas the theist, taken in the strict sense, turns more for his start and inspiration to Plato.

The causal argument
      The argument for the existence of God inferred from motion was given a more familiar form in the first of the five ways of St. Thomas Aquinas (Aquinas, Thomas, Saint), five major proofs of God that also owed much to the emphasis on the complete transcendence of God in the teaching of Plotinus, the leading Neoplatonist of the 3rd century AD, and his followers. (The word that Plotinus used for the ultimate but mysterious dependence of all things on God is emanation (emanationism); but this characterization was not understood by him, as it has been by some later thinkers, as questioning the genuine independent existence of finite things.) In the first way, Aquinas put forward the view that all movement implies, in the last analysis, an unmoved mover; and though this argument, as he understood it, presupposes certain views about movement and physical change that may not be accepted today, it does make the main point that finite processes call for some ground or condition other than themselves.

      This becomes more explicit in the second way, which proceeds from the principle that everything must have an “efficient cause”—i.e., a cause that actively produces and accounts for it—to the notion of a first cause required to avoid an infinite regress, or tracing of causes endlessly backward. As normally found, the idea of efficient causality, in respect to change and process, has many difficulties; and some would prefer to speak instead of regular or necessary sequence. But a more serious objection stresses the apparent inconsistency of thinkers who invoke a general principle of causality and then exempt the alleged first cause. As the child is apt to put it, “Who then made God?” To this a defender of St. Thomas, or at least of the present approach to the idea of God, would reply that the first cause is not supposed to be itself a member of any ordinary causal sequence but altogether beyond it, an infinite reality not itself a part of the natural or temporal order at all. This point, in fact, is what the third way, starting from the contingency of the world, brings out more explicitly. Nothing explains itself, and all other explanations fall short of showing in any exhaustive way why anything is as it is, or why there is anything at all. But it is also hard to suppose that things just happen to be. Nothing could come out of just nothing, and so the course of events as men find and explain them points to some reality that is not itself to be understood or explained in the normal way at all: it is Explanation with a capital E, as it were, that is seen to be necessitated by all that there is—of whose nature, however, nothing may be directly discerned beyond the inevitability of its being as the ultimate or unconditioned ground of all else and in this way transcendent or utterly mysterious in itself.

      This way of thinking of the being and necessity of God has been impressively presented in the mid-20th century by notable thinkers like Austin Farrer, E.L. Mascall, and H.P. Owen and also by the present writer (see below Bibliography (atheism)). Generally known as the cosmological approach to the idea of God, it has much in common with the insistence on the transcendence of God in recent theology.

The ontological argument
      Scholars have often converged upon the same theme in what appears to be a very different line of argument, namely the ontological one, with which are associated especially the names of St. Anselm (Anselm of Canterbury, Saint), first of the Scholastic philosophers (Scholasticism) (in the 11th century), and René Descartes (Descartes, René), first major modern philosopher (in the mid-17th century). Proponents of this argument (Cartesianism) try to show that the very idea of God implies his existence. God is the greatest or most perfect being. If the attribute of existence, however, is not included in man's concept of God, he can then think of something more perfect, viz., that which has existence as well. Critics, such as Gaunilo—a monk of Marmoutier—in Anselm's day and Immanuel Kant (Kant, Immanuel)—one of the major architects of modern philosophy—many centuries later, have fastened on the weakness that existence is not a predicate or attribute in the same way, at least, as colour or shape; but there have been highly ingenious attempts by influential religious thinkers of today to restate the argument in an acceptable form. (See especially the writings of Charles Hartshorne and Norman Malcolm.) Others find in the argument an oblique and needlessly elaborate way of eliciting the feeling that there must be some reality that exists by the very necessity of its own nature and to which everything else directs man's thought.

The reference to value and design
      Attempts to arrive at the idea of God in somewhat more comprehensible terms are reflected in the references to value and design in the fourth and fifth ways of St. Thomas; this approach, however, has been given a more explicit presentation and critical discussion in the works of David Hume (Hume, David), a mid-18th-century Scottish Skeptic, and in Kant. The main idea of the teleological argument (argument from design), as it is called, is that of the worth and purpose, or apparent design, to be found in the world. This purposiveness is taken to imply a supreme Designer. It has been questioned, however (by Kant, for example), whether this argument can really get started without presupposing some feature of the causal argument. The presence of seemingly purposeless features of the world and of much that is positively bad, like wickedness and suffering (evil, problem of), while always embarrassing for a theistic view, presents peculiar difficulties here. For the arguer is now throwing hostages to fortune in the shape of a special assessment of the way things actually happen, which goes far beyond the mere requirement of some ultimate ground, whatever the world appears to be like. The arguments from worth and design have, however, one considerable advantage, viz., that they provide a fairly straightforward way of learning about the nature of God and of ascribing a certain aim and character to him from one's understanding of the phenomena that he is required to explain. The supreme Designer or Architect is known from his works, especially perhaps as reflected in the lives of men; and this approach opens up one way of speaking of God, not just as mysterious power behind the world but as some reality whom man may come to know in a personal way from the way the world goes and from his understanding of what it means.

      Many thinkers in the late 19th and early 20th centuries sought to establish man's knowledge of God in the way suggested through his understanding of himself and the world; and of these the most notable and valuable still today are the British theists James Ward, a psychologist, and F.R. Tennant, a philosophical theologian. But the work of thinkers like Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, a Jesuit paleoanthropologist, and the spate of discussion that he has provoked are also relevant here; and such work, in turn, owes much—directly or otherwise—to the work of evolutionary thinkers like Samuel Alexander and Henri Bergson and of modern scientists like Julian Huxley.

The problem of particular knowledge of God
      If the central theme of traditional theism, viz., that the finite world depends in some way on one transcendent and infinite Being, can be sustained, then a crucial problem presents itself at once: the question of how a being whose essence can never be known to man—who, as infinite, is bound to be beyond the grasp of reason and to remain wholly mysterious—how such a being can be said to be known (epistemology) at all, much less known and experienced in the close and intimate personal ways that the theist makes equally central to his claim. Part of the answer is that the theist does not claim to fathom the ultimate mystery of God or to know him as he is in himself. All that is claimed on this score is that man sees the inevitability of there being God in the contingent and limited character of everything else; and though this line of thought could not be adopted for any finite existence—since one could not normally affirm in any sensible way the existence of anything without specifying in some measure, however slight, what it is like—one can, nonetheless, regard the case of God as unique and not subject to the conditions of finite intelligibility. In these ways, an insight or intuition into the being of God may be claimed without a commitment to anything about his nature beyond the sort of completeness or perfection required to account for there being limited finite things. This insight is much in line with the “deliverances of religious consciousness” in which it is claimed that God is “hidden,” is “past finding out,” that his ways are not man's ways, that he is eternal, uncreated, and so on. But the theist still has a major problem on his hands, for he also makes a central issue of the claim that God can be known—“met” and “encountered” in some way—indeed, that some very bold affirmations about God and his dealings with men may be made.

Theism and natural theology
      Theists have tried to deal with this problem in various ways. One of these ways is their use of the doctrine of analogy, which owes a great deal to the teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas. Various types of analogy are distinguished in the traditional doctrine; but the central claim is that certain predicates, such as “love,” “faithfulness,” or “justice,” may be affirmed of God in whatever way may reflect his involvement as the author of the limited realities, such as man, of which such predicates may be affirmed in the normal, straightforward way. The difficulty with this procedure is that, whatever it yields, the content of faith is still very thin and remote, far from the warm fellowship of personal relations. Most of the traditional sponsors of the doctrine admit this and contend, therefore, that the findings of their “natural theology,” as it is called, must be supplemented by that of revelation or of divine disclosure. Theism, in fact, is hardly conceivable without some doctrine of revelation. But even if the theologian says that God takes the initiative in communicating himself to man, the epistemological problem remains of how men's essentially finite minds can apprehend anything pertaining to infinite or eternal Being.

      At this point, recourse is sometimes had to authority, the authority of a sacred book, an institution, or a system of doctrines, or one of divinely implanted images. But there must at least be some initial justification of an authority, to say nothing of an evaluation of rival claims. A more attractive solution, then, especially for those who stress the personal involvement of God in men's lives, is one posed in terms of religious experience. Such experience is usually given prominence in theistic contexts. It is sometimes understood in terms of paranormal phenomena, like hearing voices or seeing visions, which have no natural origin, or like being in some peculiar psychical state. Some of the faithful believe that God literally speaks to them (or spoke in times past to prophets) in this way. A more subtle view holds that men have reason to regard certain experiences as their clue to what they should say of God in his relation to them. The question then arises of how these experiences should be recognized; and various answers are given, such as that which stresses the formative influence (within such experiences) of the initial insight into the being of God and the patterning of the experiences, in themselves and in wider ramifications, as a result. Much use is made in this context of the analogy with men's knowledge of one another. Men do not know one another's minds, it is alleged, as they know their own but only as mediated through bodily states and behaviour. So a man may come to know God, who in his essence is impenetrable to him, from the impact that he makes within experiences and events that one would otherwise understand and handle just as one does other finite occurrences. In the molding and perpetuating of such experiences, prominence is given to imagination and to the place of figurative terms and symbolism. These forms have therefore a place of special importance in theistic types of religion, the personal encounter being extended and deepened through art and literature, song, dance, myth, and ritual. This fact, in turn, presents problems for thought and practice, since the art forms and ritual must not be allowed to take wing on their own and thereby be loosed from the discipline and direction of the proper dynamic of religious life.

Theism and religious language
      Preoccupation with the forms in which religious life expresses itself has led some theistic writers to lean heavily on the contribution made to religious understanding today by studies of religious language. In some cases this concern has carried with it, as generally in much linguistic philosophy of today, a skeptical or agnostic view of the transcendent factor in religion. It is hard to see, however, how attenuations of this kind could be strictly regarded as forms of theism; though clearly, within their more restricted scope, they can retain many of the other characteristics of theism, such as the stress on personal involvement and response. This tendency is very marked in some recent studies of religion, in which the inspiration and form of theism are retained without the substance—though how long and how properly are moot points. There are others who, while retaining the transcendent reference of theism, look for the solution of the central problem less in the substance of religious awareness and in varieties of experience than in the modes of articulation and religious language. Controversy centres, to a great degree, on which of these approaches is the most fruitful.

      In the work of some theists today, the preoccupation with language is also combined with the existentialist stress on personal involvement and commitment. A good example of this approach is found in the work of I.T. Ramsey, the bishop of Durham, who, in spite of his insistence on disclosure situations, in which something peculiarly significant becomes alive to man, seemed to concede more than a theist should to the skeptical strain in recent studies of religious language.

The nature of God in modern thought
      Modern thought has thrown new light on issues, both old and new, regarding the nature of God.

Theism and incarnation (theophany)
      The core of human personality has often been thought to be man's moral existence, and, accordingly, theists have often taken this fact to be the main clue to the way they are to think of divine perfection and to the recognition of a peculiar divine involvement in the world. Prominence is thus accorded to the high ethical teaching and character of saints and prophets, who have a special role to play in transmitting the divine message. In some religions this tendency culminates in doctrines of incarnation, of God manifesting himself expressly in refined or perfected human form. This trend is peculiarly marked in the Christian religion (Christianity), in which the claim is usually made that a unique and “once for all” incarnation of God has occurred in Christ. Incarnational claims seem certainly to take their place easily in some main forms of theism. The vindication of such claims, however—especially today—relies much on consideration of the personal factor in religion generally.

      For these and related reasons, the theist today may find himself calling to his aid certain other disciplines that centre upon men as persons, such as psychology and anthropology. Not all of the forms and findings of these studies favour the theist, and he should take special note of their challenge when they seem hostile, for they may touch him at his tenderest spot. He may, on the other hand, find in such studies, and certain general literature that borders on kindred themes, substantial help in reconstructing his case in the full context of contemporary thought and culture.

Humanism and transcendence
      It is indeed from certain modern studies of man and his environment that some of the most disturbing challenges to the theist have come. For it has been argued that the very idea of God, as well as the more specific forms that it takes, emanate from man's emotional needs for succour and comfort. It is in fact man himself, it is said, who has created God in his own image, and the attempt is made to substantiate this view from accounts of the proclivity of men, especially in early times, to personify natural objects—rivers, trees, mountains, and so forth—and, in due course, to confer peculiar properties upon them, leading in time to the notion of some superbeing in whom these powers and properties are concentrated. The classical statement of this position appeared before the development of anthropology and the modern systematic study of religions, viz., in David Hume's (Hume, David) essay “The Natural History of Religion” (1757). This short but splendidly lucid and challenging work set the pattern for the more scientific and empirical studies of religion that began to take shape in the 19th century in pioneer work by E.B. Tylor, a British ethnologist and anthropologist, in his Primitive Culture (1871), and by Sir James Frazer, an ethnographer and historian of religion, in his Golden Bough (1890–1915). But a corrective to this approach was soon provided by other scholars equally renowned, who started from the historical and empirical evidence available to them at the time. Andrew Lang (Lang, Andrew), a Scottish litterateur, drew attention to the phenomenon, among very early peoples, of the High God, a Supreme Being who created himself and the earth and dwelt at one time on earth. John H. King, in The Supernatural: Its Origin, Nature and Evolution (1892), stressed the importance of the element of mystery in all religions, and another pioneer of religious anthropology, R.R. Marett (Marett, Robert R.), showed how extensively the savage ascribes the mysteries of life and power to a supernatural source. Lucien Lévy-Bruhl (Lévy-Bruhl, Lucien), a French sociologist, noted the pervasiveness of prelogical factors in primitive mentality, and Rudolf Otto (Otto, Rudolf), the most famous name in this context, found evidence in early forms of religion of a response to “the wholly other,” the mysterium tremendum et fascinans.

The idea of a finite God
      Concern with the problem of evil (evil, problem of)—i.e., with reconciling the existence of evil with that of a good God (theodicy)—becomes acute for thinkers who rest their case mainly on what they find in the world around them; and this has led many to retreat to the notion of a finite God, according to which the world may be under the direction of a superior being who is nonetheless limited in power, though not in goodness. This is a serious alternative to the idea of a supreme and unlimited source of all reality as found in the usual forms of theism. Indeed, it is a moot point whether the idea of a finite God should be classified as a form of theism. It does come close to traditional theism, however, in its insistence on the unity and absolute benevolence of God. There are clearly advantages in the notion of God as a limited being, especially where evil is concerned; for though one could still insist that God intends nothing that is not wholly good, he can now account for extensive suffering and other ills on the basis of the limits to God's power. He is doing his utmost, the finitist holds, but there are things—refractory materials or explicitly evil powers—that he has not yet subdued, though hopefully he will eventually do so. There is also induced in this way a sense of urgency in man's own obligation to cooperate with God—to be a “fellow worker.” God will clearly need his help though he himself is in the vanguard of the battle against evil. Thus, those who incline to the idea of a finite God usually have been activist in thought and practice.

      There are also grave difficulties to be met. For if a thinker has recourse to the idea of God simply to account for what is otherwise bewildering in the finite course of things, he may find no warrant for the inference involved and indeed may find himself desperately clinging to what is sometimes called “the God of the gaps” (i.e., of the gaps in man's explanations). If, on the other hand, he starts from the inherently incomplete character of finite explanation as such, or from the contingency of finite things, nothing short of an infinite or absolute God will meet the case. In addition, the usual attitude of religious people, or of what is sometimes known as “the religious consciousness,” is that of a profound assurance and serenity that presupposes that God is “all in all” and beyond any possibility of being thwarted. It is also questionable whether the attitude of worship is appropriate for a limited being, however superior he may be to man.

      Among the outstanding advocates of the idea of a finite God were, at the turn of the 20th century, the U.S. Pragmatist William James (James, William) and some of his disciples, notably Ralph Barton Perry. Thus, it is not surprising that a closely similar notion arising in the mid-20th century finds its main inspiration and support in the United States, viz., in the work of process philosophers, such as Charles Hartshorne (Hartshorne, Charles) and Schubert Ogden, who have developed some of the leading ideas of A.N. Whitehead (Whitehead, Alfred North), an eminent metaphysician. In their view, God is himself in process of fulfillment in some kind of identification with the world, which at the same time leaves him distinct in some sense from the universe, which he permeates and unifies. There are grave and admitted paradoxes in this view; and, in spite of the remarkable ingenuity of its advocates and their logical nimbleness, it is not clear that the paradoxes can be sustained nor that the difficulties that are shared with the simpler notion of a finite God can be overcome. Much in recent religious thought centres on this issue.

Theism in Islām
      The Muslim faith owes much to the Semitic outlook from which the Old Testament and Christianity arose. It centres on a transcendent personal deity; but, in its regard for the holiness and majesty of God, it rejects incarnational doctrines as a form of blasphemy. There is, however, a paradoxical side to one form of Islām: while insisting that God is all in all, it sometimes tends to represent all of man's own actions as the action of God within him and thus has some tendency to identify man with God. This tendency, most marked in the mysticism of the Ṣūfīs (Ṣūfism), seems, as respects its monism, to veer away from theism but seems, as respects the sense of devotion and personal excitation that it inspires, to be in line with the more explicit forms of theism. In its main form, Islām, with its quite exceptional sense of the transcendence of God, is one of the most distinctively theistic religions, though at odds with the incarnational factor in Christian theism.

Theism in Eastern thought
      The trend toward the testing of theistic thought in the crucible of the special disciplines was continued not only in further anthropological studies (see The Worship of the Sky-God, by E.O. James) but also in extensive scholarly studies and translations of the sacred books of the great religions of the East.

Hindu (Hinduism) theism
      It was noted, for example, that the Vedic hymns that appear in the earliest Hindu scriptures contain significant intimations of a sense of “the wonder of existence,” “the outpourings,” as Savepalli Radhakrishnan (Radhakrishnan, Sarvepalli), the former philosopher-president of India, has expressed it, “of poetic minds who were struck by the immensity of the universe and the inexhaustible mystery of life.” Note was taken also of early manifestations of henotheism, a view that exalts several deities to the first place. The theme of some one supreme reality, the first principle, or the supreme self becomes more explicit in the Upaniṣads (Upanishad), ancient Hindu scriptures, while retaining a sense of its ineffableness. One hears of “the way of silence” and of the ultimate absorption of all into the one supreme reality, the “one who breathes breathless.” This one is variously conceived in its relation to finite things; and although the transcendent reference is rarely absent, there is not the same recognition of the distinctness of finite beings that there is in Western theism or of the eternal self being involved in the world in a personal way. The Upaniṣads have, in fact, a variety of themes and emphases, tending generally toward a monistic and mystical philosophy; but on occasion the theistic element is very marked, as in the Kaṭha and the Śvetāśvatara books of the Upaniṣads. The absolutist and the theistic views are not always felt to be exclusive. This climate of thought has set the course for much of subsequent Hinduism, in which, along with the persistence of the monistic strain, the theistic note is sounded much more distinctly, especially in the doctrine and practice of bhakti—devotion to a personal God who bestows grace. In the famous Bhagavadgītā (Bhagavadgita) (probably 3rd or 4th century BC), a classic of religious literature, and in the teaching of the Brahmin Rāmānuja (11th century), considered the founder of the Viśiṣṭādvaita (qualified nondualism) school, the flowering of the more theistic side of Hinduism is found. In the Śaiva-siddhānta theology of South Indian Śaivism (Shaivism) (a major cult of Hinduism), there is a firm insistence that the soul, in being united with God, is not annihilated or negated but only fused into the likeness of God, who, in turn, is always in loving pursuit of the soul. This doctrine makes the system “perhaps the highest form of theism that India was ever to develop” (R.C. Zaehner). In the closing words of the Bhagavadgītā is an insistence on a love of God for man and of man for God that represents a decisive turning point in the history of Hinduism:

Think on me, worship me, sacrifice to me, pay me homage, so shalt thou come to me, I promise thee truly, for I love thee well. Give up all things of dharma, turn to me only as thy refuge. I will deliver thee from all evil. Have no care.

      This theology has been well reflected in the 20th century in the devotionalism of Gandhi (Gandhi, Mohandas Karamchand) and in the writings of Sri Aurobindo (Aurobindo, Śrī), a philosopher and Yoga devotee, which reflect an indwelling of the divine within the world and a summons to high moral endeavour on the part of man that comes close to theism without explicitly accepting it.

Buddhism and theism
      The same diversity of strains is found in Buddhism. Though Buddhism was at one time regarded as an atheistic religion leading to total elimination of self in a state of Nirvāṇa, a close examination of the evidence—in the Pāli Tipiṭaka, for example, the canon of the Theravāda (Theravada) school of Buddhism—leads to a revision in favour of the view that the seeming negativism of early Buddhist scriptures and the rejection of metaphysics reflect chiefly the caution arising from a profound recognition of the characterless elusiveness of the transcendent. And although the Buddhist doctrine of compassion and its rigorous intellectual and moral discipline may lack something of the warmth of a close personal commitment, the Buddhist adoration of the Buddha and of the bodhisattvas (those on their way to Enlightenment) afforded much scope to the religious responses that find their full expression in overt theism. This trend became more marked in the more popular forms of Buddhism and in the mythologies that centre upon the idea of the bodhisattvas.

Theism in other religions
      In the same way, the seeming agnosticism of Confucian religion (Confucianism) is qualified by its teaching about a power from beyond the world working for justice within it, a “Heaven-ordained relationship” that provides the basis of ethics and induces a deep consciousness of individuality. This trend became intensified in the conflations that resulted from the extension of Buddhism into China.

      In the doctrines of Sikhism, a religion of the eastern Punjab that combines certain Muslim and Hindu elements, stress is laid upon personal awareness of God as a central and unifying factor in religion. In doctrine though not always in practice, however, the Sikhs reject every notion of an avatar, or incarnation. The religion of the Jains (Jainism) is nontheistic in theory, but the great figures of its tradition come to function as gods in popular religion. For a period in ancient Persia, there was established in the teaching of Zoroaster (Zoroastrianism) (Zarathushtra) a form of ethical monotheism in which the god Ahura Mazdā is the creator of the physical and moral world—though limited, for a time at least, by an opposing principle of evil (Ahriman).

      The clue to the theistic element in the religions of primitive peoples may well be found in an observation by H.H. Farmer, a British philosophical theologian:

We may surmise that at moments of living prayer and worship there is in primitive man a turning to a god as if he were in fact the one and only God, though without any expressly formulated denial of the existence of others; for the time being, the god worshipped fills the whole sphere of the divine.

Hywel David Lewis

Additional Reading
A classic statement of God's transcendence is A.M. Farrer, Finite and Infinite, 2nd ed. (1959), a difficult but essential book on theism; C.A. Campbell, On Selfhood and Godhood (1957), is an exceptionally lucid presentation that allows for the distinctness of finite beings; see also further statements in William Temple, Nature, Man and God (1934); H.H. Farmer, God and Men (1947); and H.D. Lewis, Philosophy of Religion (1965). A. Seth Pringle-Pattison presents the more traditional Idealist view in The Idea of God in the Light of Recent Philosophy (1920). An Idealism stressing the immediate awareness of other minds and of God is found in W.E. Hocking, The Meaning of God in Human Experience (1912); a presentation similarly starting from Empiricism and science that culminates in a “Cosmic Teleology” is that of F.R. Tennant, Philosophical Theology, 2 vol. (1928–30). E.S. Brightman, The Problem of God (1930), treats God as a limited being (finitism).

* * *


Universalium. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую
Synonyms:

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Theism — Theism, in its most inclusive usage, is the belief in at least one deity. Some narrower usages specify that the deity believed in be a distinct identifiable entity, thereby being contrasted with pantheism. Other narrower usages specify that the… …   Wikipedia

  • theism —    Theism is the doctrine that God exists or that a divine being exists.    See theism, classical; theism, open    Further reading: Aquinas 1963 80; Hill, Daniel J. 2005; Swinburne 1993a …   Christian Philosophy

  • Theism — The ism, n. [From Gr. ? God; probably akin to ? to pray for, ? spoken by God, decreed: cf. F. th[ e]isme. Cf. {Enthusiasm}, {Pantheon}, {Theology}.] The belief or acknowledgment of the existence of a God, as opposed to {atheism}, {pantheism}, or… …   The Collaborative International Dictionary of English

  • Theism — The ism (th[=e] [i^]z m), n. [NL. & E. thea tea + ism.] (Med.) The morbid condition resulting from the excessive use of tea. [Webster 1913 Suppl.] …   The Collaborative International Dictionary of English

  • theism — (n.) belief in a deity, 1670s; see THEIST (Cf. theist). Meaning belief in one god (as opposed to POLYTHEISM (Cf. polytheism)) is recorded from 1711 …   Etymology dictionary

  • theism — ► NOUN ▪ belief in the existence of a god or gods, specifically of a creator who intervenes in the universe. Compare with DEISM(Cf. ↑deistic). DERIVATIVES theist noun theistic adjective. ORIGIN from Greek theos god …   English terms dictionary

  • theism — [thē′iz΄əm] n. [ THE(O) + ISM] 1. belief in a god or gods 2. belief in one God; monotheism: opposed to PANTHEISM, POLYTHEISM 3. belief in one God viewed as creator and ruler of the universe and known by revelation: distinguished from DEISM theist …   English World dictionary

  • Theism — the view that there is one or more gods or goddesses.[13] More specifically, it may also mean the belief in God, a god, or gods, who is/are actively involved in maintaining the Universe. A theist can also take the position that he does not have… …   Mini philosophy glossary

  • theism — Belief in the existence of God. Theism is also a morbid condition brought on by excessive tea drinking, but this is a different sense of the word, or an instance of homonymy . See also deism, monotheism, polytheism, and different topics within… …   Philosophy dictionary

  • theism — See deism. See deism, theism …   Dictionary of problem words and expressions

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”